Read More
Date: 4-1-2017
1387
Date: 5-1-2017
1483
Date: 12-1-2017
791
|
The central problem in symbolic logic is the investigation of the process of reasoning. In mathematics, as in every deductive science, there are no assertions of "absolute" truth. Rather, a certain set of propositions is assumed without proof, and from this set, other propositions are derived by logical reasoning. For example, when we assert the truth of the Pythagorean theorem, we mean simply that it can be deduced from the axioms of the Euclidean geometry of the plane. It is not true, for instance, for triangles on the surface of a sphere.
We now proceed to investigate those processes which will be accepted as valid in the derivation of a proposition, called the conclusion, from other given propositions, called the premises. We define an argument to be a process by which a conclusion is formed from given premises. An argument is valid if and only if the conjunction of the premises implies the conclusion. That is, the argument which yields a conclusion r from premises p1, P2, ... , pn is valid if and only if the proposition (P1…..P2….. pn) → r is a tautology. In general, there are three ways to check the validity of a given argument. The first is to check it directly from the definition by using a truth table; that is, for the argument above, the truth-table method is used to show that (P1…..P2….. . pn) → r is a tautology. The second method is to show that the proposition (P1…..P2….. . pn) → r can be reduced to 1, using the standard methods of simplification. The third, and often the simplest of the three, is to reduce the argument to a series of arguments each of which is known to be valid as a result of previous checking. Two of the most frequently used valid arguments are the rule of detachment (also called modus ponens) and the law of syllogism. The rule of detachment is given by the form
We will use this schematic arrangement in stating all our arguments. The premise, or premises, will be listed first and the conclusion will follow beneath a horizontal line. Reasons or explanations may be written to the right of each proposition.
The law of syllogism is given by the form
The validity of this argument, as well as of modus ponens, may be easily checked by either of the first two methods previously mentioned.
It is important to note that an argument is valid or invalid independently of the truth or falsity of the conclusion. For example, consider the following two arguments. The first is valid although the conclusion is false, and the second is invalid although the conclusion is true.
In addition to the rule of modus ponens, and the law of syllogism, the valid argument forms in Table 1-1 have either been checked in previous problems or can readily be verified.
TABLE 1-1
FORMS OF VALID ARGUMENT
In checking the validity of any argument, we will also assume that it is permissible to use either of the following rules of substitution.
RULE 1. Any valid argument which involves a propositional variable will remain valid if every occurrence of a given variable is replaced by a specific proposition.
RULE 2. Any valid argument will remain valid if any occurrence of a proposition is replaced by an equivalent proposition.
From the definition of a valid argument, it follows at once that in addition to any given premises, we may use as a premise any tautology in the algebra of propositions.
In checking a given argument for validity, if it is found or suspected that the argument is invalid, a proof of invalidity can be given more easily than by constructing the entire truth table related to the argument.
It is sufficient to exhibit a particular set of truth values for the propositions involved for which the premises are all true and the conclusion is false. This does nothing more than demonstrate that one row in the truth table, if constructed, would contain a 0 and hence the argument is invalid.
EXAMPLE 1. Show that the following argument is valid:
First solution: We construct the truth table for the function
f = [p(p →q)(q →r)] →r.
(See Table 1-2.) Since the f column contains only 1's, the argument is valid.
TABLE 1-2
TRUTH TABLE FOR THE ARGUMENT OF EXAMPLE 1
Second solution: Consider the function f as above:
Since f reduces to 1, this also shows that the argument is valid.
Third solution: Consider the following sequence of arguments:
This sequence of valid arguments shows again, and with less work than either of the first two methods, that the given argument was valid.
EXAMPLE 2. Cheek the validity of the argument
Solution: The argument
is valid by the law of syllogism. Since r →q' is equivalent to q → r', an application of Substitution Rule 2 completes the proof.
EXAMPLE 3. Show that the following argument is not valid:
Solution: If p is true, q is false, and r is false, then each of the premises is true but the conclusion is false. Hence the argument is invalid.
|
|
علامات بسيطة في جسدك قد تنذر بمرض "قاتل"
|
|
|
|
|
أول صور ثلاثية الأبعاد للغدة الزعترية البشرية
|
|
|
|
|
مدرسة دار العلم.. صرح علميّ متميز في كربلاء لنشر علوم أهل البيت (عليهم السلام)
|
|
|