Grammar
Tenses
Present
Present Simple
Present Continuous
Present Perfect
Present Perfect Continuous
Past
Past Continuous
Past Perfect
Past Perfect Continuous
Past Simple
Future
Future Simple
Future Continuous
Future Perfect
Future Perfect Continuous
Passive and Active
Parts Of Speech
Nouns
Countable and uncountable nouns
Verbal nouns
Singular and Plural nouns
Proper nouns
Nouns gender
Nouns definition
Concrete nouns
Abstract nouns
Common nouns
Collective nouns
Definition Of Nouns
Verbs
Stative and dynamic verbs
Finite and nonfinite verbs
To be verbs
Transitive and intransitive verbs
Auxiliary verbs
Modal verbs
Regular and irregular verbs
Action verbs
Adverbs
Relative adverbs
Interrogative adverbs
Adverbs of time
Adverbs of place
Adverbs of reason
Adverbs of quantity
Adverbs of manner
Adverbs of frequency
Adverbs of affirmation
Adjectives
Quantitative adjective
Proper adjective
Possessive adjective
Numeral adjective
Interrogative adjective
Distributive adjective
Descriptive adjective
Demonstrative adjective
Pronouns
Subject pronoun
Relative pronoun
Reflexive pronoun
Reciprocal pronoun
Possessive pronoun
Personal pronoun
Interrogative pronoun
Indefinite pronoun
Emphatic pronoun
Distributive pronoun
Demonstrative pronoun
Pre Position
Preposition by function
Time preposition
Reason preposition
Possession preposition
Place preposition
Phrases preposition
Origin preposition
Measure preposition
Direction preposition
Contrast preposition
Agent preposition
Preposition by construction
Simple preposition
Phrase preposition
Double preposition
Compound preposition
Conjunctions
Subordinating conjunction
Correlative conjunction
Coordinating conjunction
Conjunctive adverbs
Interjections
Express calling interjection
Grammar Rules
Preference
Requests and offers
wishes
Be used to
Some and any
Could have done
Describing people
Giving advices
Possession
Comparative and superlative
Giving Reason
Making Suggestions
Apologizing
Forming questions
Since and for
Directions
Obligation
Adverbials
invitation
Articles
Imaginary condition
Zero conditional
First conditional
Second conditional
Third conditional
Reported speech
Linguistics
Phonetics
Phonology
Semantics
Pragmatics
Linguistics fields
Syntax
Morphology
Semantics
pragmatics
History
Writing
Grammar
Phonetics and Phonology
Semiotics
Reading Comprehension
Elementary
Intermediate
Advanced
Teaching Methods
Teaching Strategies
Wh-movement, EPP and the Attract Closest Principle
المؤلف:
Andrew Radford
المصدر:
Minimalist Syntax
الجزء والصفحة:
197-6
5/12/2022
2407
Wh-movement, EPP and the Attract Closest Principle
An important question raised by the analysis outlined above is what triggers wh-movement. Chomsky (1998, 1999, 2001) suggests that an [EPP] feature is the mechanism which drives movement of wh-expressions to spec-CP. More specifically, he maintains that just as T in finite clauses carries an [EPP] feature requiring it to be extended into a TP projection containing a subject as its specifier, so too C in wh-questions carries an [EPP] feature requiring it to be extended into a CP projection containing a wh-expression as its specifier. Some evidence that complementizers can indeed have an [EPP] feature comes from sentences like (25b) below:
If we suppose that expletive there is inserted in a sentence like (25a) in order to satisfy an [EPP] feature carried by T, and if we further suppose (in the light of arguments offered by Landau 2002) that from is a complementizer in structures like (25b), it seems plausible to suppose that there is used in (25b) to satisfy an [EPP] feature carried by the complementizer from. More generally, the [EPP] feature of a head H requires H to have a specifier which matches one or more of the features carried by H: so, for example, since a finite T carries person and number features, its [EPP] feature requires it to have a subject with matching person and/or number features; and if we assume that C in a wh-clause contains a [WH] feature, this will mean that its [EPP] feature requires it to have a wh-specifier
We can illustrate how the EPP analysis of wh-movement works by looking at the derivation of the bracketed interrogative complement clause in (26) below:
The bracketed wh-question clause in (26) is derived as follows. The verb going is merged with its complement where (which is a locative adverbial pronoun) to form the VP going where. The present-tense auxiliary are is then merged with the resulting VP to form the T-bar are going where. The pronoun you is in turn merged with this T-bar to form the TP you are going where. A null complementizer [C ø] is subsequently merged with the resulting TP. Since the relevant clause is a wh-question, C contains a [WH] feature. In addition, since English (unlike Chinese) is the kind of language which requires wh-movement in ordinary wh-questions, C also has an [EPP] feature requiring it to have a specifier. Given these assumptions, merging C with its TP complement will form the C-bar in (27) below (where features are CAPITALIZED and enclosed within square brackets):
(A minor descriptive detail is that the locative adverbial pronoun where is categorized here as a PRN/pronoun, though it could equally be assigned to the category ADV/adverb.) The [WH] feature of C allows C to attract a wh-expression. The [EPP] feature of C requires C to project as its specifier an expression which has a feature which matches some feature of C: since C carries a [WH] feature, this amounts to a requirement that C must project a wh-specifier. On the assumption that the wh-pronoun where carries a [WH] feature, this means that C will attract the wh-pronoun where to move from the VP-complement position which it occupies in (27) above to CP-specifier position. If we suppose that the [WH] and [EPP] features carried by C are deleted (and thereby inactivated) once their requirements are satisfied (deletion being indicated by strikethrough), we derive the structure (28) below (assuming, too, that the phonological features of the trace of the moved wh-constituent where are also deleted):
There is no auxiliary inversion (hence no movement of the auxiliary are from T to C) because (28) is a complement clause, and an interrogative C only carries a [TNS] feature triggering auxiliary inversion in main clauses.
Chomsky (2001) maintains that movement is simply another form of merger. He refers to merger operations which involve taking an item out of the lexical array and merging it with some other constituent as external merge, and to movement operations by which an item contained within an existing structure is moved to a new position as internal merge. Accordingly, the structure (27) is created by a series of external merger operations, and is then mapped into (28) by an internal merger operation (namely wh-movement).
The EPP analysis of wh-movement has interesting implications for the syntax of multiple wh-questions which contain two or more separate wh-expressions. (See Dayal 2002 for discussion of the semantic properties of such questions.) A salient syntactic property of such questions in English is that only one of the wh-expressions can be preposed – as we see from the fact that in the bracketed interrogative clauses in (29) below, only who can be preposed and not what:
In order to get a clearer picture of what is going on in the bracketed complement clause here, let’s consider what happens when we arrive at the stage of derivation shown in (30) below:
By hypothesis, the null complementizer [C ø] at the root/top of the tree contains a [WH] feature requiring the clause to contain a wh-expression, and an [EPP] feature requiring it to have a specifier matching the [WH] feature carried by C (i.e. to have a wh-specifier). In order to satisfy this requirement, C searches for a wh-expression within the C-bar structure immediately containing it in (30). Since it is who rather than what which is preposed in (30) and since who is closer to C than what, let’s suppose that C attracts the closest wh-expression which it c-commands. This requirement is a consequence of a principle of Universal Grammar (adapted from Chomsky 1995, p. 297) which we can outline informally as follows:
(Chomsky 1995, p. 311 proposes an analogous principle which he terms the Minimal Link Condition and formulates it thus: ‘K attracts only if there is no
closer to K than
, such that K attracts
.’) It follows from ACP that a C carrying [WH, EPP] features will trigger movement of the closest constituent carrying a wh-feature to C. So, since who appears to be closer to C than what in (30), it is who which is attracted to move to spec-CP. Using rather different but equivalent terminology, sentences like (29) can be said to show a superiority effect in that C has to attract the ‘highest’ constituent of the relevant type. An alternative to the ACP account is to suppose that the relevant effect is a consequence of an Intervention Constraint to the effect that in a structure of the form [. . . X . . . [. . . Y . . . [. . . Z . . .]]] X cannot attract Z if there is a constituent Y of the same type as Z which intervenes between X and Z: on this view, the presence of who intervening between C and what in (30) prevents C from attracting what to move to spec-CP.
One question this raises, however, is how we determine whether who or what is closer to C. At first sight, it might seem as if there is a simple way of doing this – namely by counting the number of nodes you have to go through if you try and get from one constituent to the other by climbing along the branches of the tree. In order to get from the C node containing the null complementizer to the PRN node containing who, we have to go through six other nodes (C-bar, TP, T-bar, VP, CP, TP), whereas in order to get from C to the PRN node containing what we have to go through eight other nodes (C-bar, TP, T-bar, VP, CP, TP, T-bar, VP): hence, this simple node-counting procedure tells us that who is closer to C than what, and consequently it is who which is attracted by C in (30) and not what, in accordance with the Attract Closest Principle.
However, the idea that grammars might employ a counting algorithm of some kind in order to determine how syntactic operations apply is implausible, since counting otherwise seems to play no part in syntax – for instance, we find no syntactic operations which target (e.g.) the fourth constituent in a sentence, or which invert the second and third constituents. Moreover, the notion of counting is alien to the spirit of Minimalism, which assumes that the only primitive relations in syntax are structural relations like contain and c-command which come about via merger. From a theoretical perspective, it is therefore preferable to define relative closeness in terms of structural relations. There are a variety of ways of doing this (see Fitzpatrick 2002), but for present purposes we can make the following assumption (where X, Y and Z are three different constituents):
If we take X to be the main clause C in (30), Y to be who and Z to be what, we can see that who is closer to the main-clause C than what in terms of the definition of closeness in (32) because C c-commands both who and what but what is contained within a maximal projection (= the VP done what) which does not contain who. In consequence, the Attract Closest Principle (31) correctly predicts that what cannot undergo wh-movement in (30), but who can, with who thereby moving into spec-CP and deriving the structure shown below (assuming deletion of the [WH] and [EPP] features of C, and of the trace copy of the moved pronoun who):
In short, the assumption that C carries [WH] and [EPP]features, in conjunction with the Attract Closest Principle (31) and the ancillary assumption that the [EPP] and [WH] features of C are deleted (and thereby inactivated) once a wh-expression has been moved to spec-CP, accounts for the pattern of grammaticality found in multiple wh-questions like (29). (Note that our focus on English here means that we do not deal with languages like Bulgarian which allow multiple wh-fronting: see Grewendorf 2001 and Boˇskovi´c 2002a for alternative accounts of multiple wh-fronting.)
الاكثر قراءة في Syntax
اخر الاخبار
اخبار العتبة العباسية المقدسة

الآخبار الصحية
